Announcement

Collapse
No announcement yet.

Can the Sciences Help Us to Make Wise Ethical Judgments?

Collapse
X
 
  • Filter
  • Time
  • Show
Clear All
new posts

  • Can the Sciences Help Us to Make Wise Ethical Judgments?

    Skeptical Inquirer
    26 Oct. 2004

    Can the Sciences Help Us to Make Wise Ethical Judgments?

    Scientific knowledge has a vital, if limited, role to play in shaping
    our moral values and helping us to frame wiser judgments. Ethical
    values are natural and open to examination in the light of evidence and
    reason.

    Paul Kurtz


    I.
    Can science and reason be used to develop ethical judgments? Many
    theists claim that without religious foundations, "anything goes," and
    social chaos will ensue. Scientific naturalists believe that secular
    societies already have developed responsible ethical norms and that
    science and reason have helped us to solve moral dilemmas. How and in
    what sense this occurs are vital issues that need to be discussed in
    contemporary society, for this may very well be the hottest issue of
    the twenty-first century.

    Dramatic breakthroughs on the frontiers of science provide new powers
    to humans, but they also pose perplexing moral quandaries. Should we
    use or limit these scientific discoveries, such as the cloning of
    humans? Much of this research is banned in the United States and
    restricted in Canada. Should scientists be permitted to reproduce
    humans by cloning (as we now do with animals), or is this too
    dangerous? Should we be allowed to make "designer babies?" Many
    theologians and politicians are horrified by this; many scientists and
    philosophers believe that it is not only inevitable but justifiable
    under certain conditions. There were loud cries against in vitro
    fertilization, or artificial insemination, only two generations ago,
    but the procedure proved to be a great boon to childless couples. Many
    religious conservatives are opposed to therapeutic stem-cell research
    on fetal tissues, because they think that "ensoulment" occurs with the
    first division of cells. Scientists are appalled by this censorship of
    scientific research, since the research has the potential to cure many
    illnesses; they believe those who oppose it have ignored the welfare of
    countless numbers of human beings. There are other equally
    controversial issues on the frontiers of science: Organ transplants-who
    should get them and why? Is the use of animal organs to supply parts
    for human bodies wrong? Is transhumanism reforming what it means to be
    human? How shall we control AIDS-is it wicked to use condoms, as some
    religious conservatives think, or should this be a high priority in
    Africa and elsewhere? Does global warming mean we need a radical
    transformation of industry in affluent countries? Is homosexuality
    genetic, and if so, is the denial of same-sex marriage morally wrong?
    How can we decide such questions? What criteria may we draw upon?

    II.
    Many adhere today to the view that ethical choices are merely
    relativistic and subjective, expressing tastes; and you cannot disputes
    tastes (de gustibus non disputandum est). If they are emotive at root,
    no set of values is better than any other. If there is a conflict, then
    the best option is to persuade others to accept our moral attitudes, to
    convert them to our moral feelings, or, if this fails, to resort to
    force.

    Classical skeptics denied the validity of all knowledge, including
    ethical knowledge. The logical positivists earlier in the twentieth
    century made a distinction between fact, the appropriate realm of
    science, and value, the realm of expressive discourse and imperatives,
    claiming that though we can resolve descriptive and theoretical
    questions by using the methods of science, we cannot use science to
    adjudicate moral disputes. Most recently, postmodernists, following the
    German philosopher Heidegger and his French followers, have gone
    further in their skepticism, denying that there is any special validity
    to humanistic ethics or indeed to science itself. They say that science
    is merely one mythological construct among others. They insist that
    there are no objective epistemological standards; that gender, race,
    class, or cultural biases likewise infect our ethical programs and any
    narratives of social emancipation that we may propose. Who is to say
    that one normative viewpoint is any better than any other, they demand.
    Thus have many disciples of multicultural relativism and subjectivism
    often given up in despair, becoming nihilists or cynics. Interestingly,
    most of these well-intentioned folk hold passionate moral and political
    convictions, but when pushed to the wall, will they concede that their
    own epistemological and moral recommendations likewise express only
    their own personal preferences?

    The problem with this position is apparent, for it is impaled on one
    horn of a dilemma, and the consequence of this option is difficult to
    accept. If it is the case that there are no ethical standards, then who
    can say that the Nazi Holocaust and the Rwandan, Cambodian, or Armenian
    genocides are evil? Is it only a question of taste that divides sadists
    and masochists on one side from all the rest on the other? Are slavery,
    the repression of women, the degradation of the environment by
    profit-hungry corporations, or the killing of handicapped people
    morally impermissible, if there are no reliable normative standards? If
    we accept cultural relativity as our guide, then we have no grounds to
    object to Muslim law (sharia), which condones the stoning to death of
    adulteresses.

    III.
    What is the position of those who wish to draw upon science and reason
    to formulate ethical judgment? Is it possible to bridge the gap and
    recognize that values are relative to human interests yet allow that
    they are open to some objective criticisms? I submit that it is, and
    that upon reflection, most educated people would accept them. I choose
    to call this third position "objective relativism" or "objective
    contextualism"; namely, values are related to human interests, needs,
    desires, and passions-whether individual or socio-cultural-but they are
    nonetheless open to scientific evaluation. By this, I mean a form of
    reflective intelligence that applies to questions of principles and
    values and that is open to modification of them in the light of
    criticism. In other words, there is a Tree of Knowledge of Good and
    Evil, which bears fruit, and which, if eaten and digested, can impart
    to us moral knowledge and wisdom.

    In what sense can scientific inquiry help us to make moral choices? My
    answer to that is it does so all the time. This is especially the case
    with the applied sciences: medicine, dentistry, nursing, pharmacology,
    psychiatry, and social psychology; and also in the policy sciences:
    economics, education, political science; and such interdisciplinary
    fields as criminology, gerontology, etc. Modern society could not
    function without the advice drawn from these fields of knowledge, which
    make evaluative judgments and recommend prescriptions. They advise what
    we ought to do on a contextual basis.

    Nonetheless, there are the skeptical critics of this position, who deny
    that science per se can help us or that naturalistic ethics is
    possible. I think that those critics are likewise mistaken and that
    naturalism is directly relevant to ethics. My thesis is that an
    increase in knowledge can help us to make wiser decisions. By
    knowledge, I do not refer simply to philosophical analysis but
    scientific evidence. It would answer both the religionist, who insists
    that you cannot be moral unless you are religious, and the
    subjectivist, who denies there is any such thing as ethical knowledge
    or wisdom.

    Before I outline this position, let me concede that the skeptical
    philosophical objections to deriving ethics from science have some
    merit. Basically, what are they? The critics assert that we cannot
    deduce ethics from science, i.e., what ought to be the case from what
    is the case. A whole series of philosophers from David Hume to the
    emotivists have pointed out this fallacy. G.E. Moore, at the beginning
    of the twentieth century, characterized this as "the naturalistic
    fallacy" [1] (mistakenly, I think).

    But they are essentially correct. The fact that science discovers that
    something is the case factually does not make it ipso facto good or
    right. To illustrate: (a) Charles Darwin noted the role of natural
    selection and the struggle for survival as key ingredients in the
    evolution of species. Should we conclude, therefore, as Herbert Spencer
    did, that laissez-faire doctrines ought to apply, that we ought to
    allow nature to take its course and not help the handicapped or the
    poorer classes? (b) Eugenicists concluded earlier in the century that
    some people are brighter and more talented than others. Does this
    justify an elitist hierarchical society in which only the best rule or
    eugenic methods of reproduction be followed? This was widely held by
    many liberals until the fascists began applying it in Germany with dire
    consequences.

    There have been abundant illustrations of pseudoscientific
    theories-monocausal theories of human behavior that were hailed as
    "scientific"-that have been applied with disastrous results. Examples:
    (a) The racial theories of Chamberlain and Gobineau alleging Aryan
    superiority led to genocide by the Nazis. (b) Many racists today point
    to IQ to justify a menial role for blacks in society and their
    opposition to affirmative action. (c) The dialectical interpretation of
    history was taken as "scientific" by Marxists and used to justify class
    warfare. (d) Environmentalists decried genetics as "racist" and thought
    that changes in species should only be induced by modifications of the
    environment. Thus, one has to be cautious about applying the latest
    scientific fad to social policy.

    We ought not to consider scientific specialists to be especially gifted
    or possessed with ethical knowledge nor empower them to apply this
    knowledge to society-as B.F. Skinner in Walden II and other utopianists
    have attempted to do. Neither scientist-kings nor philosopher-kings
    should be entrusted to design a better world. We have learned the risks
    and dangers of abandoning democracy to those wishing to create a Brave
    New World. Alas, all humans-including scientists-are fallible, and
    excessive power may corrupt human judgment. Given these caveats, I
    nevertheless hold that scientific knowledge has a vital, if limited,
    role to play in shaping our moral values and helping us to frame wiser
    judgments of practice--surely more, I would add, than our current
    reliance on theologians, politicians, military pundits, corporate CEOs,
    and celebrities!

    IV.
    How and in what sense can scientific inquiry help us?

    I wish to present a modified form of naturalistic ethics. By this, I
    mean that ethical values are natural; they grow out of and fulfill
    human purposes, interests, desires, and needs. They are forms of
    preferential behavior evinced in human life. "Good," "bad," "right,"
    and "wrong" relate to sentient beings, whether human or otherwise.
    These values do not reside in a far-off heaven, nor are they deeply
    embedded in the hidden recesses of reality; they are empirical
    phenomena.

    The principle of naturalism is based on a key methodological criterion:
    We ought to consider our moral principles and values, like other
    beliefs, open to examination in the light of evidence and reason and
    hence amenable to modification.

    We are all born into a sociocultural context; and we imbibe the values
    passed on to us, inculcated by our peers, parents, teachers, leaders,
    and colleagues in the community.

    I submit that ethical values should be amenable to inquiry. We need to
    ask, are they reliable? How do they stack up comparatively? Have they
    been tested in practice? Are they consistent? Many people seek to
    protect them as inviolable truths, immune to inquiry. This is
    particularly true of transcendental values based on religious faith and
    supported by custom and tradition. In this sense, ethical inquiry is
    similar to other forms of scientific inquiry. We should not presuppose
    that what we have inherited is true and beyond question. But where do
    we begin our inquiry? My response is, in the midst of life itself,
    focused on the practical problems, the concrete dilemmas, and
    contextual quandaries that we confront.

    Let me illustrate by refer to three dilemmas. I do so not in order to
    solve them but to point out a method of inquiry in ethics. First,
    should we exact the death penalty for people convicted of murder? The
    United States is the only major democracy that still demands capital
    punishment. What is the argument for the death penalty? It rests on two
    basic premises: (a) A factual question is at issue: capital punishment
    is effective in deterring crime, especially murder; and (b) the
    principle of justice that applies is retributive. As the Old Testament
    adage reads, "Whatever hurt is done, you shall give life for life, eye
    for eye, tooth for tooth. . . ." [2]

    The first factual premise can be resolved by sociological studies, by
    comparing the incidence of murder in those states and nations that have
    the death penalty in force and those that do not and by states and
    nations before and after the enactment or abrogation of the death
    penalty. We ask, has there been an increase or a decrease in murder?
    If, as a matter of fact, the death penalty does not restrain or inhibit
    murder, would a person still hold his view that the death penalty ought
    to be retained? The evidence suggests that the death penalty does not
    to any significant extent reduce the murder rate, especially since most
    acts of murder are not deliberate but due to passion or are an
    unexpected result of another crime, such as robbery. Thus, if one bases
    his or her belief in capital punishment primarily on the deterrence
    factor, and it does not deter, would one change one's belief? The same
    consideration should apply to those who are opposed to the death
    penalty: Would they change their belief if they thought it would deter
    excessive murder rates? These are empirical questions at issue. And the
    test of a policy are its consequences in the real world. Does it
    achieve what it sets out to do?

    There are, of course, other factual considerations, such as: Are many
    innocent people convicted of crimes they did not commit (as was
    recently concluded in the State of Illinois)? Is capital punishment
    unfairly applied primarily to minorities? This points to the fact that
    belief in capital punishment is, to some extent, a function of
    scientific knowledge concerning the facts of the case. This often means
    that such measures should not be left to politicians or jurors alone to
    decide; the scientific facts of the case are directly relevant.

    The second moral principle of retributive justice is far more difficult
    to deal with, for this may be rooted in religious conviction or in a
    deep-seated tribal sense of retaliation. If you injure my kin, it is
    said, I can injure yours; and this is not purely a factual issue. There
    are other principles of justice that are immediately thrown into
    consideration. Those opposed to the death penalty say that society
    "should set a humane tone and not itself resort to killing." Or again,
    the purpose of justice should be to protect the community from future
    crimes, and alternative forms of punishment, perhaps lifetime
    imprisonment without the right of parole, might suffice to deter crime.
    Still another principle of justice is relevant: Should we attempt,
    where possible, to rehabilitate the offender? All of the above
    principles are open to debate. The point is, we should not block
    inquiry; we should not say that some moral principles are beyond any
    kind of re-evaluation or modification. Here, a process of deliberation
    enters in, and a kind of moral knowledge emerges about what is
    comparatively the best policy to adopt.

    Another example of the methods of resolving moral disputes is the
    argument for assisted suicide in terminal cases, in which people are
    suffering intolerable pain. This has become a central issue in the
    field of medical ethics, where medical science is able to keep people
    alive who might normally die. I first saw the emergence of this field
    thirty years ago, when I sponsored a conference in biomedical ethics at
    my university and could find very few, if any, scholars or scientists
    who had thought about the questions or were qualified experts. Today,
    it is an essential area in medicine. The doctor is no longer taken as a
    patriarchal figure. His or her judgments need to be critically
    examined, and others within the community, especially patients, need to
    be consulted. There are here, of course, many factual questions at
    issue: Is the illness genuinely terminal? Is there great suffering? Is
    the patient competent in expressing his or her long-standing
    convictions regarding his or her right to die with dignity? Are there
    medical and legal safeguards to protect this system against abuse?

    Our decision depends on several further ethical principles: (a) the
    informed consent of patients in deciding whether they wish treatment to
    continue; (b) the right of privacy, including the right of individuals
    to have control of their own bodies and health; and (c) the criterion
    of the quality of life.

    One problem we encounter in this area is the role, again, of
    transcendental principles. Some people insist, "God alone should decide
    life-and-death questions, not humans." This principle, when invoked, is
    beyond examination, and for many people it is final. Passive euthanasia
    means that we will not use extraordinary methods to keep a person
    alive, where there is a longstanding intent expressed in a living will
    not to do so. Active euthanasia will, under certain conditions, allow
    the patient, in consultation with his physician, to hasten the dying
    process (as practiced in Oregon and the Netherlands). The point is,
    there is an interweaving of factual considerations with ethical
    principles, and these may be modified in the light of inquiry, by
    comparing alternatives and examining consequences in each concrete
    case.

    I wish to illustrate this process again by referring to another issue
    that is hotly debated today: Should all cloning research be banned? The
    Canadian legislature, in March 2004, passed legislation that will put
    severe restrictions on such scientific research. The bill is called "An
    Act Respecting Assisted Human Reproduction" (known as C-56), and it
    makes it a criminal offense to engage in therapeutic cloning, to
    maintain an embryo outside a woman's body for more than fourteen days,
    to genetically manipulate embryos, to choose the gender of offspring,
    to sell human eggs and sperm, or to engage in commercial surrogacy. It
    also requires that in vitro embryos be created only for the purpose of
    creating human beings or for improving assisted human-reproductive
    procedures. Similar legislation was passed by the U.S. House of
    Representatives and is before the Senate. It is still being heatedly
    debated. It includes the prohibition of reproductive cloning as well as
    therapeutic stem-cell research. Two arguments against reproductive
    cloning are as follows: (a) It may be unsafe (at the present stage of
    medical technology) and infants born may be defective. This factual
    objection has some merit. (b) There is also a moral objection saying
    that we should not seek to design children. Yet we do so all the time,
    with artificial insemination, in vitro fertilization, and surrogate
    motherhood. We already are involved in "designer-baby" technology, with
    amniocentesis, pre-implantation, genetic testing, and chorionic villus
    sampling (the avoiding of unwanted genes by aborting fetuses and
    implanting desirable embryos).

    If it were to become safe, would reproductive cloning become
    permissible? I can think of situations where we might find it
    acceptable-for example, if couples are unable to conceive by normal
    methods.

    It is the second area I mentioned above that is especially telling-the
    opposition to any forms of embryonic stem-cell research. Proponents
    maintain that this line of research may lead to enormous benefits by
    curing a wide range of diseases such as Parkinson's disease,
    Alzheimer's, or juvenile diabetes. Adult stem cells are now being used,
    but embryonic stem cells may provide important new materials. The
    criterion here is consequential: that positive outcomes may result.
    Opponents maintain that this type of research is "immoral" because it
    is tampering with human persons possessed of souls. Under this
    interpretation, "ensoulment" occurs at the moment of conception. This
    is said to apply to embryos, many of which, however, are products of
    miscarriages or abortions. Does it also apply once the division of stem
    cells occurs? Surely a small collection of cells, which is called a
    blastocyst, is not a person, a sentient being, or a moral agent prior
    to implantation. Leon Kass, chair of President Bush's Council on
    Bioethics, believes that human life cannot be treated as a commodity
    and it is evil to manufacture life. He maintains that all human life,
    including a cloned embryo, has the same moral status and dignity as a
    person from the moment of conception.

    This controversy pits two opposing moral claims: (a) the view that
    stem-cell research may be beneficent because of its possible
    contributions to human health (i.e., it might eliminate debilitating
    diseases) versus (b) an ethic of revulsion against tampering with
    natural reproductive processes. At issue here are the questions of
    whether ensoulment makes any sense in biology and whether personhood
    can be said to have begun at such an early stage, basically a
    transcendental claim that naturalists object to on empirical grounds.
    These arguments are familiar in the abortion debate; it would be
    unfortunate if they could be used to censor scientific stem-cell
    research.

    This issue is especially relevant today, for transhumanists say that we
    are discovering new powers every day that modify human nature, enhance
    human capacities, and extend life spans. We may be able to extend
    memory and increase human perception and intelligence dramatically by
    silicon implants. Traditionalists recoil in horror, saying that
    post-humanists would have us transgress human nature. We would become
    cyborgs.

    But we already are, to some extent: we wear false teeth, eyeglasses,
    and hearing aids; we have hair grafts, pacemakers, organ transplants,
    artificial limbs, and sex-change/sexual reassignment operations and
    injections; we use Viagra to enhance sexual potency or mega-vitamins
    and hormone therapy. Why not go further? Each advance raises ethical
    issues: Do we have the reproductive freedom and responsibility to
    design our children by knowing possible genetic disorders and
    correcting them before reproduction or birth?

    V.
    This leads to an important distinction between two kinds of values
    within human experience. Let me suggest two possible sources: (a)
    values rooted in unexamined feelings, faith, custom, or authority, held
    as deep-seated convictions beyond question, and (b) values that are
    influenced by cognition and informed by rational inquiry.

    Naturalists say that scientific inquiry enables us to revise our
    values, if need be, and to develop, where appropriate, new ones. We
    already possess a body of prescriptive judgments that have been tested
    in practice in the applied sciences of medicine, psychiatry,
    engineering, educational counseling, and other fields. Similarly, I
    submit that there is a body of prescriptive ethical judgments that has
    been tested in practice and that constitutes normative knowledge; and
    new normative prescriptions are introduced all the time as the sciences
    progress.

    The question is thus raised, what criteria should we use to make
    ethical choices? This issue is especially pertinent today for those
    living in pluralistic societies such as ours, where there is diversity
    of values and principles.

    In formulating ethical judgments, we need to refer to what I have
    called a "valuational base." [3] Packed into this referent are the
    pre-existing de facto values and principles that we are committed to;
    but we also need to consider empirical data, means-ends relationships,
    causal knowledge, and the consequences of various courses of action. It
    is inquiry that is the instrument by which we decide what we ought to
    do and that we should develop in the young. We need to focus on moral
    education for children; we wish to structure positive traits of
    character and also the capacity for making reflective decisions. There
    are no easy recipes or simple formulae that we can appeal to, telling
    us what we ought to do in every case. There are, however, what W.D.
    Ross called prima facie general principles of right conduct, the common
    moral decencies, a list of virtues, precepts, and prescriptions,
    ethical excellences, obligations, and responsibilities, which are
    intrinsic to our social roles. But how they work out in practice
    depends on the context at hand, and the most reliable guide for mature
    persons is cognitive inquiry and deliberation.

    Conservative theists have often objected to this approach to morality
    as dangerous, given to "debauchery" and "immorality." Here, there is a
    contrast between two different senses of morality: (a) the
    obedience/authoritarian model, in which humans are expected to follow
    moral absolutes derived from ancient creeds, and (b) the encouragement
    of moral growth, implying that there are within the human species
    potential moral tendencies and cognitive capacities that can help us to
    frame judgments.

    For a naturalistic approach, in the last analysis, ethics is a product
    of a long evolutionary process. Evolutionary psychology has pointed out
    that moral rules have enabled human communities to adapt to threats to
    their survival. This Darwinian interpretation implies a biological
    basis for reciprocal behavior- epigenetic rules-according to E.O.
    Wilson (1998). [4] The social groups that possessed these rules
    transmitted them to their offspring. Such moral behavior provides a
    selective advantage. There is accordingly an inward propensity for
    moral behavior, moral sentiments, empathy, and altruism within the
    species.

    This does not deny that there are at the same time impulses for selfish
    and aggressive tendencies. It is a mistake, however, to read in a
    doctrine of "original sin" and to say that human beings are by nature
    sinful and corrupt. I grant that there are individuals who lack moral
    empathy; they are morally handicapped. Some may even be sociopaths. The
    salient point is that there are genetic potentialities for good and
    evil; but how they work out and whether beneficent behavior prevails is
    dependent on cultural conditions. Both our genes (genetics) and memes
    (social patterns of enculturation) are factors that determine how and
    why we behave the way we do. We cannot simply deduce from the
    evolutionary process what we ought to do. What we do depends in part
    upon the choices we make. Thus, we still have some capacity for free
    choice. Though we are conditioned by environmental and biogenetic
    determinants, we are still capable of cognitive processes of selection,
    and rationality and intentionality play a causative role. (Note: There
    is a considerable scientific literature that supports this evolutionary
    view. See Daniel Dennett, Freedom Evolves [New York: Viking, 2003] and
    Darwin's Dangerous Idea [New York: Simon and Schuster, 1995]; Brian
    Skyrm, Evolution of the Social Contract [Cambridge: Cambridge
    University Press, 1996], Robert Wright, The Moral Animal [New York:
    Pantheon Books, 1994] and Nonzero [New York: Vintage Books, 2001], Matt
    Ridley, The Origins of Virtue [New York: Viking, 1996], and Elliott
    Sober and David Sloan Wilson, Unto Others [Cambridge, Massachusetts:
    Harvard University Press, 1998].)

    Ethical precepts need not be based upon transcendental grounds or
    dependent upon religious faith. Undoubtedly, the belief that they are
    sacred may strengthen moral duties for many persons, but it is not
    necessary for everyone.

    I submit that it is time for scientists to recognize that they have an
    opportunity to contribute to naturalistic ethics. We stand at an
    interesting time in human history. We have great power to ameliorate
    the human condition. Biogenetic engineering, nanotechnology, and space
    research open new opportunities for humankind to create a better world.


    Yet there are those today who wish to abandon human reason and freedom
    and return to mythological legends of our premodern existence,
    including their impulses of aggres- sion and self-righteous vengeance.
    I submit that the Enlightenment is a beacon whose promise has not been
    fulfilled and that humankind needs to accept the responsibility for its
    own future.

    Conclusion
    A caveat is in order. In the last analysis, some degree of skepticism
    is a necessary antidote to all forms of moral dogmatism. We are
    continually surrounded by self-righteous moralists who claim that they
    have the Absolute Truth, Moral Virtue, or Piety or know the secret path
    to salvation and wish to impose their convictions on all others. They
    are puffed up with an inflated sense of their own rectitude as they
    rail against unbenighted immoral sinners who lack their moral faith.
    These moral zealots are willing to repress or even sacrifice anyone who
    stands in their way. They have in the past unleashed conquering armies
    in the name of God, the Dialectic, Racial Superiority, Posterity, or
    Imperial Design. Skepticism needs to be applied not only to religious
    and paranormal fantasies but to other forms of moral and political
    illusions. These dogmas become especially dangerous when they are
    appealed to in order to legislate morality and are used by powerful
    social institutions, such as a state or church or corporation, to
    enforce a particular brand of moral virtue. Hell hath no fury like the
    self-righteous moral fanatic scorned.

    The best antidote for this is some skepticism and a willingness to
    engage in ethical inquiry, not only about others' moral zeal, but about
    our own, especially if we are tempted to translate the results of our
    own ethical inquiries into commandments. The epistemological theory
    that I propose is based upon methodological principles of skeptical
    scientific inquiry, and it has important moral implications. For in
    recognizing our own fallibility, we thereby can learn to tolerate other
    human beings and to appreciate their diversity and the plurality of
    lifestyles. If we are prepared to engage in cooperative ethical
    inquiry, then perhaps we are better prepared to allow other individuals
    and groups some measure of liberty to pursue their own preferred
    lifestyles. If we are able to live and let live, then this can best be
    achieved in a free and open democratic society. Where we differ, we
    should try to negotiate our divergent views and perhaps reach common
    ground; and if this is impractical, we should at least attempt to
    compromise for the sake of our common interests. The method of ethical
    inquiry requires some intelligent and informed examination of our own
    values as well as the values of others. Here we can attempt to modify
    attitudes by an appeal to cognitive beliefs and to reconstruct them by
    an examination of the relevant scientific evidence. Such a
    give-and-take of constructive criticism is essential for a harmonious
    society. In learning to appreciate different conceptions of the good
    life, we are able to expand our own dimensions of moral awareness; and
    this is more apt to lead to a peaceful world.

    By this, I surely do not mean to imply that anything and everything can
    or should be tolerated or that one thing is as good as the next. We
    should be prepared to criticize moral nonsense parading as virtue. We
    should not tolerate the intolerable. We have a right to strongly
    object, if need be, to those values or practices that we think are
    based on miscalculation, misconception, or that are patently false or
    harmful. Nonetheless, we might live in a better world if inquiry were
    to replace faith; deliberation, passionate commitment; and education
    and persuasion, force and war. We should be aware of the powers of
    intelligent behavior, but also of the limitations of the human animal
    and of the need to mitigate the cold, indifferent intellect with the
    compassionate and empathic heart. Thus, I conclude that within the
    ethical life, we are capable of developing a body of melioristic
    principles and values and a method of coping with problems
    intelligently. When our ethical judgments are based on rational and
    scientific inquiry, they are more apt to express the highest reaches of
    excellence and nobility and of civilized human conduct. We are in sore
    need of that today.

    In This Issue
    Buy this back issue
    Can the Sciences Help Us to Make Wise Ethical Judgments?
    The Columbia University 'Miracle' Study: Flawed and Fraud
    The Campeche, Mexico 'Infrared UFO' Video
    Lady Homeopathy Strikes Back . . . But Science Wins Out
    Review: What the #$*! Do We Know?
    Notes
    1. G.E. Moore. Principia Ethica (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
    1903).

    2. See Exodus 21.

    3. Kurtz, Paul (ed.). The New Skepticism: Inquiry and Reliable
    Knowledge (Amherst, New York: Prometheus, 1992), chapter 9.

    4. Wilson, E.O. Consilience (New York: Alfred Knopf, 1998).

    About the Author

    Paul Kurtz is a professor emeritus at the State University of New York
    at Buffalo, and chairman of the Center for Inquiry - Transnational.
    This article is a portion of the keynote address delivered at the
    conference on "Science and Ethics" sponsored by the Center for Inquiry
    in Toronto, Ontario, on May 13, 2004.
Working...
X