Announcement

Collapse
No announcement yet.

Among The Intellectualoids

Collapse
X
 
  • Filter
  • Time
  • Show
Clear All
new posts

  • Among The Intellectualoids

    AMONG THE INTELLECTUALOIDS
    Immanuel Kant for Dummies
    By James Bowman

    American Spectator
    Oct 30 2006

    The most fundamental of all the liberal principles handed down to us
    from the Enlightenment and the very cornerstone of our civilization
    is the "categorical imperative" of Immanuel Kant: namely, that one
    cannot act on that maxim which one cannot will to be universal. In
    other words, if it's OK for me to do it, it has to be OK for everybody
    to do it. If it's not OK for everybody to do it, then it's not OK
    for me to do it either. This principle is so deeply ingrained in us,
    along with the contempt we feel for what we call " hypocrisy" when
    people violate it, that we take it for granted. I was having dinner the
    other night with a learned and cultured man, an internationally famed
    historian of somewhat conservative tendencies, when the conversation
    turned to the North Korean nuclear test. "What I just can't get past,"
    this man said, "is that we are saying it's OK for us to have nuclear
    weapons, but it's not OK for the North Koreans or the Iranians."

    Glen Suarez of London writes in a similar vein to the Times: "How can
    we condemn North Korea for seeking to acquire nuclear weapons when we
    possess them and say that we wish to upgrade them? How can Tony Blair
    condemn the North Korean regime for 'disregarding the concerns of
    neighbours and the wider international community' when he and George
    Bush did the same when invading Iraq?" Neither of these men mention
    Kant, but of course it was the Kantian principle they were appealing
    to as an absolute bar against efforts by leaders in America or Britain
    to prevent potential terrorist states or backers of terrorists from
    acquiring nuclear weapons or doing other things which might pose a
    threat to their countries.

    A moment's thought will show us that the Kantian principle cannot
    apply in international relations, at least not unless we are prepared
    to adopt a thoroughgoing pacifist and (I would say) suicidal policy
    by disarming and disbanding our armed forces and refusing to fight
    against those who wish us harm. So long as we admit that a nation has
    the right to defend itself, we must also admit that it is necessary
    to adopt a different standard for ourselves and for our enemies. It
    is OK and probably unavoidable for us to bomb them, for example, while
    it is very definitely not OK for them to bomb us. Leave aside for the
    moment the question of whether or not it can be right to bomb them, if
    we are to fight them at all and so preserve ourselves, our people and
    property and our way of life, we must be prepared to do things to them
    that we should not hesitate to deplore if and when they did them to us.

    The Kantian principle really has its origins in the revolutionary
    Christian notion that it is wrong for us to consider ourselves ahead
    of other people. We should put our duty to others first -- or at least
    treat them no worse than we treat ourselves. Under the old Christian
    dispensation, it was recognized that this kind of saintliness had to
    be reserved for, well, saints, and those who chose to live lives that
    were not of this world. They belonged, to use the Augustinian imagery,
    to the City of God rather than the City of Man.

    But the Enlightenment began with the idea that that kind of saintliness
    ought not to be reserved for a special few but ought to be expected
    of, even required of, everybody. That's hard enough to live up
    to in our personal lives. To live up to it in matters of war and
    peace and international relations is impossibly utopian -- unless,
    of course, you're a pacifist and are prepared to give up the right
    of self-defense.

    ****

    The Nobel Prize for literature given this year to the Turkish novelist
    Orhan Pamuk caused some of his fellow Turks great annoyance.

    "The prize was not given to Pamuk for being a writer, nor to his
    works," said the conservative Kemal Kerincsiz who advocated prosecuting
    Pamuk "for directly insulting the Turkish nation" over the wish to
    acknowledge genocide practiced by the Turks against the Armenians
    in 1915. When Pamuk was prosecuted (he got off on a technicality),
    he denied that he had insulted Turkey. "But what if it is wrong?" he
    said. "Right or wrong, do people not have the right to express their
    ideas peacefully." Ah! But in an honor culture of the sort that still
    holds sway in Turkey and other historically Islamic nations, the insult
    is not dependent on right or wrong. This is a question subordinate to
    that of honor or dishonor, and the charge itself, irrespective of its
    truth or falsity, brings dishonor on the nation. In such a culture,
    it remains true as it once was in ours, that if a bad act is not made
    public to the shame of the doer, then it didn't really happen.

    I wonder, too, if Mr. Pamuk's profession makes him vulnerable to this
    kind of misunderstanding. The novelist almost by his very existence
    must privilege the individual psyche over the demands of the group
    when they come into conflict. A novel without psychological reality
    -- as opposed to the honor culture's demand for conformity with which
    that reality is bound to come into conflict -- is not really a novel at
    all. Novels and novelists naturally belongs to our Western, post-honor
    world, which is why there are so few novelists in the Islamic one
    and why those there are, like Mr. Pamuk or the late Naguib Mahfouz
    are so often in trouble and even risk their lives merely to continue
    doing what we take it for granted novelists should do -- that is,
    in Mr. Pamuk's own phrase "to express their ideas peacefully." It
    sounds reasonable to us, but not to those whose world-view is formed
    by honor in this basic, even primitive form.

    James Bowman is a resident scholar at the Ethics and Public Policy
    Center, media essayist for the New Criterion, and The American
    Spectator's movie critic. He is the author of the new book, Honor:
    A History (Encounter Books).

    http://www.spectator.org/dsp_article.asp? art_id=10555
Working...
X