Announcement

Collapse
No announcement yet.

The Limits To Partition

Collapse
X
 
  • Filter
  • Time
  • Show
Clear All
new posts

  • The Limits To Partition

    THE LIMITS TO PARTITION
    by Michael C. Horowitz and Alex Weisiger

    International Security
    Spring 2009

    Michael C. Horowitz and Alex Weisiger are Assistant Professors of
    Political Science at the University of Pennsylvania.

    Carter Johnson is a Ph.D. candidate at the University of Maryland,
    College Park.

    To the Editors (Michael C. Horowitz and Alex Weisiger write): In his
    article "Partitioning to Peace: Sovereignty, Demography, and Ethnic
    Civil Wars," Carter Johnson argues that partition is frequently the
    best available policy response to ethnic civil wars. By creating a
    new measure of the degree of demographic unmixing achieved through
    partition, Johnson demonstrates that mere changes in sovereignty are
    insufficient to produce peaceful outcomes. He contends, however, that
    "complete" separation of the two sides will help to bring peace. He
    concludes that partition is a useful tool for the international
    peacemaker, with the caveat that it "should be considered, however,
    only where populations are already largely separated at the time of
    intervention, or where interveners are prepared to separate groups
    using mass population transfers." 1 He interprets these findings as
    "strong evidence for advocates of partition (p. 168)."

    We believe that Johnson's caveat is more important than it appears at
    first blush, and that its practical implication is to render partition
    an effectively useless policy tool. The partition prescription is
    grounded in the logic of the ethnic security dilemma, but there is
    empirical evidence that genuine conflicts of interest exist alongside
    security dilemma fears. In this context, participants will resist the
    population transfers necessary for effective partition. Given that the
    international community is not going to carry out population transfers
    in the face of violent resistance, effective partition is unlikely to
    occur except through ethnic cleansing during war. Johnson's data are
    consistent with these observations: effective partition rarely happens,
    and when it does, it is through ethnic cleansing rather than organized
    population transfers. In short, successful partitions ratify military
    outcomes. Furthermore, when we consider that even effective partition
    has not guaranteed peace, these observations strongly suggest that
    the international community should retain its current position toward
    partition of tacit acquiescence in a small number of unavoidable cases,
    but should not promote partition as a strategy to end ongoing wars.

    The partition prescription is grounded in the logic of the ethnic
    security dilemma, in which conflict breaks out in an intermixed ethnic
    setting because each side fears that the other is going to attack
    it and therefore sees a strategic benefit to striking first. Neutral
    partition, if possible, is a logical solution to this problem because
    it eliminates incentives for preemptive action and facilitates each
    side's efforts to defend itself. Given these effects, partition
    logically should be welcomed by participants. 2

    That observation, however, points to a significant problem with the
    ethnic security dilemma and the prescription of partition. From
    Kashmir to Kirkuk, ethnic conflicts have involved not only fear
    of attack but fundamental disagreements about who should control
    important pieces of territory. In other words, security motives
    interact with predation to produce distinct but overlapping incentives
    for fighting. 3 This observation has important implications for the
    viability of partition as a strategy. Partition depends on outside
    interveners being willing to facilitate the transfer of populations,
    which they are reluctant to do given the violations of international
    law involved (p. 150). If the conflict in question involves not only
    security fears but competition for control of disputed territory,
    the international force facilitating partition does not merely act
    in the context of violence; it becomes a target. As examples such as
    Somalia in 1993 and Rwanda in 1994 show, there is little historical
    evidence that outside interveners are willing to suffer these sorts of
    costs to facilitate an outcome from which they do not directly benefit.

    Given competition over territory, voluntary population transfers
    are also a chimera, which Johnson acknowledges when he states that
    "all of the complete cases" of partition "involved large-scale forced
    population transfers during the countries' wars, with the possible
    exception of Bangladesh." 4 If the international community will
    not carry out involuntary transfers and the participants will not
    accept voluntary ones, then ethnic cleansing--held up by partition
    advocates as worse than their recommendation--is the only way that
    population transfers will occur. 5 From this perspective, advocacy
    for partition becomes advocacy for signing off on ethnic cleansing
    after the fact. That is very different than arguing that partition
    should be a preferable policy choice.

    These observations are significant when we turn to Johnson's
    empirics. Johnson takes issue with Nicholas Sambanis's finding
    that partition has not been associated with more peaceful postwar
    outcomes. He argues that this finding did not fairly test the partition
    argument, because many of the cases that Sambanis coded as partitions
    did not meet the standards laid out by partition advocates. 6 Johnson
    categorizes Sambanis's cases of partition into two groups: those in
    which partition involved the ethnic separation that theory indicates
    was necessary, and those in which ethnic unmixing did not accompany
    the change in sovereignty. Consistent with theory, Johnson finds that
    the greater the degree of unmixing, the better the postwar outcome,
    although the strength of this finding is limited by "the statistical
    problem that, as yet, there have been too few partitions" (p. 160).

    The observation that there have been few "complete" partitions is more
    than just a statistical problem, however. Our theoretical discussion
    indicates that partition will almost never be a viable policy, at best
    merely ratifying preexisting military outcomes. Closer examination
    of the evidence bears that argument out. Of the seventeen cases
    highlighted by Johnson in the post-World War II era, only six count
    as complete partitions: the separation of Bangladesh from Pakistan
    in 1971, the partition of Cyprus in 1974, the establishment of
    Eritrea in 1991, the Russian-backed creation of Abkhazia and South
    Ossetia in Georgia in 1993 and 1994, and the Armenian acquisition
    of Nagorno-Karabakh in 1994 (ibid.). Setting aside the sui generis
    case of Bangladesh, in which geographical separation between East
    and West Pakistan limited opportunities for further violence, all of
    Johnson's six cases experienced significant involuntary population
    transfers. The partition of Cyprus involved the disorganized mass
    transfer of ethnic Greeks and Turks from the two parts of the island,
    far closer to ethnic cleansing than partition. Similarly, the Armenians
    cemented their conquest of Nagorno-Karabakh by ethnically cleansing
    the Azeris, while the Azeris responded by forcing out Armenians in
    their midst. 7 In the conflicts in both South Ossetia and Abkhazia,
    large numbers of Georgians (initially the majority in Abkhazia)
    were ethnically cleansed with the aid of the Russians. 8 Finally, the
    Ethiopia-Eritrea conflict also featured significant ethnic cleansing,
    and yet it ended not because of unmixing but because the Soviets
    withdrew military support for Ethiopia, forcing it into settlement
    negotiations to ratify the military outcome. 9

    Moreover, the evidence that even "complete" partition limits subsequent
    violence is exceptionally weak. The partition of Ethiopia was followed
    only seven years later by a severe interstate war, which in two years
    killed 100,000 people, roughly two-thirds of the total who died in
    the decade and a half of the previous war. 10 Johnson acknowledges
    the problematic nature of this case (pp. 161-162), but it raises
    the further concern that even should partition prove possible it
    may not provide the benefits that advocates expect. Furthermore,
    the fighting in South Ossetia and Abkhazia in August 2008--after the
    publication of Johnson's article--underlines the limits of partition
    in preventing violence. Given a total of six "complete" partitions
    in his data set, the observation of significant fighting in three
    provides little reason to think that even successful separation of
    populations will prevent a return to violence.

    Of course, part of the appeal of the partition hypothesis is the claim
    that no other option exists. 11 Yet Sambanis's data, on which Johnson
    relies, belie this point. To evaluate the efficacy of partition,
    Johnson focuses on whether war has recurred within two or five
    years from the time of partition and whether lower-level violence has
    occurred within those same periods. Of eighty ethnic wars, fifty-seven
    did not return to war within two years of termination, and fifty-two
    remained without war after a five-year period. Lower-level violence
    was more common, but still thirty-two cases avoided even that through
    the first two years, with thirty-one sustaining peace through five
    years. Partition is not the only way to achieve peace.

    We do not wish to deny that there may well be reason to acquiesce to
    unpalatable outcomes after the fact. Civil wars are a rough business,
    and there will inevitably be times when it is preferable to tacitly
    acquiesce to a new reality than to force a return to the previous
    situation or to pretend that nothing has changed. But there is a
    significant difference between tacitly acquiescing when no other
    option is available and actively promoting those outcomes from the
    start. The knowledge that the international community will legitimate,
    or at least accept, ethnic cleansing after the fact provides reason
    for leaders to consider adopting that policy when they otherwise would
    not have. 12 In other words, the moral hazard problems with a policy
    of partition are severe.

    Johnson is to be lauded for advancing and empirically substantiating
    an important revision to the partition argument. We differ from
    him, however, in the implications of that revision. The rarity of
    "successful" partitions is, to us, an indicator that partition is
    not a good prescription. Real partitions are rare because the ethnic
    security dilemma is not the only source of conflict at work in ethnic
    civil wars, and predation provides strong incentives to resist the
    sorts of population transfers that Johnson argues are necessary for
    partition to work, while even successful partition does not guarantee
    peace. Far better, then, to recognize what Johnson's evidence really
    shows--that partition is truly an option of last resort.

    --Michael C. Horowitz Philadelphia, Pennsylvania

    --Alex Weisiger Philadelphia, Pennsylvania

    Carter Johnson Replies:

    I want to begin by thanking Michael Horowitz and Alex Weisiger for
    their constructive comments. Scholars' understanding of partition
    has long benefited from precisely this kind of exchange, enabling
    more informed decisionmaking on a topic that influences millions
    of civilian lives. My response proceeds with a brief review of the
    aims and conclusions set forth in my 2008 article, 1 highlighting a
    fundamental area of agreement between the authors and me. I then move
    to areas of disagreement, drawing on the data used in my article to
    demonstrate the policy relevance of partition even if the international
    community is not prepared to implement forced population transfers.

    In my article I argue that "complete" partitions--those that create
    a separate ethnic homeland and completely separate warring ethnic
    groups--produced peaceful outcomes for at least the first five years
    following the end of hostilities. This finding challenges the only
    previous cross-national study that systematically examined partition
    and confirmed empirically what partition advocates have long argued. 2
    Giver that 60 percent of ethnic civil wars between 1945 and 2004
    experienced deadly conflict renewal within the first five years,
    the benefits of "complete" partition are worthy of policymakers'
    consideration. 3

    Horowitz and Weisiger argue that "complete" partition is essentially a
    "useless policy tool" because civilians will resist forced transfers,
    and "the international community is not going to carry out population
    transfers in the face of violent resistance." This is an important
    point, and I agree that forced population transfers are unlikely to
    receive support from Western powers. I also agree that this limits
    the policy usefulness of partition, a fact I acknowledged in my
    article (p. 167). Still, not all forms of complete partition require
    the international community to forcibly move civilians to ensure
    long-term peace.

    REDRAWING OF BORDERS The ethnic security dilemma argues that
    ethnic groups separate from one another in wartime. Therefore,
    by the time the international community chooses to act, which can
    take months and sometimes years, it may not need to engage in forced
    population transfers because separation may already have been largely
    accomplished. Instead, the international community can redraw borders
    to minimize the number of minority groups in the emerging postpartition
    states.

    Kosovo's partition from Serbia provides a useful example. The 1999
    conflict largely separated the ethnic Kosovar and Serb populations,
    but instead of drawing the borders to reflect this reality, NATO
    and its partners maintained the prewar institutional borders of
    the Kosovar autonomous region, leaving a significant Serb minority
    within the Western-recognized borders of today's Kosovo. That region
    experienced a large-scale renewal of deadly conflict in May 2004 and
    remains dangerously unstable today; although officially under the
    control of Pristina, the region is in fact under the partial control
    of Belgrade. Instead of forcing the Serb populations from Kosovo,
    the international community could redraw the northern border to
    allow most of the Serb minority to join rump Serbia. There would
    still be small Serbian enclaves in Kosovo but, as I argue below,
    this is unlikely to cause widespread violence.

    Evidence from ethnic civil war terminations between 1945 and 2004
    suggests that even partitions that leave small numbers of an ethnic
    minority behind are also successful at maintaining the peace. As I
    noted in my article, six cases of "complete" partition have occurred
    since 1945, but this finding was based on a highly restrictive
    definition of "complete"--those reaching at least 95 percent on
    the Postpartition Ethnic Homogeneity Index (PEHI) (p. 160). If all
    of the PEHI scores are ranked from highest to lowest, however, one
    finds that none of the ten highest-scoring countries experienced a
    recurrence of conflict in the first five years after the cessation of
    hostilities (Cyprus 1974, Georgia-Abkhazia 1993, Pakistan-Bangladesh
    1971, Georgia-South Ossetia 1992, Ethiopia-Eritrea 1991, Azerbaijan
    1994, Bosnia 1995, Yugoslavia-Croatia 1995, Israel 1948, and
    India 1948). This includes countries with a PEHI score in the 50s
    (p. 160). In other words, partitions that "largely" (as opposed to
    "completely") separate ethnic groups are also likely to bring about
    an enduring peace, making the task for the international community
    much easier and therefore more practical.

    THE THEORETICAL FOUNDATION OF PARTITION Horowitz and Weisiger also
    argue that the ethnic security dilemma alone is the grounding logic
    of partition. I disagree. Although the ethnic security dilemma is
    a core component part of the partition argument, there are other
    theoretical bases as well. First, as I mention in the article,
    Alexander Downes draws on the realist school, emphasizing the
    importance of establishing separate states to maintain long-term
    peace (p. 149). 4 The creation of separate states addresses the
    fear of each side over the other's intentions even where demographic
    separation is achieved. Second, establishing separate states solves
    the problem of credible commitments, because neither side needs to
    decommission its weapons. The problem of credible commitments has
    been identified as a central obstacle in ending civil wars. 5 Third,
    Thomas Chapman and Phil Roeder recently presented an institutionalist
    argument to support partition, arguing that independence, not autonomy,
    is most beneficial for establishing long-term peace. 6 This widened
    theoretical explanation for partition might explain why complete
    and near-complete partitions are successful: a combination of both
    sovereignty and demography is central for the establishment and
    maintenance of peace after ethnic civil war.

    LONG-TERM VERSUS SHORT-TERM PEACE Finally, Horowitz and Weisiger note
    that some of the conflicts I examined in my article recurred after
    the five-year limit. This is a legitimate point, although it occurred
    in two, not three cases: the "conflict" in Abkhazia in August 2008
    caused only one soldier's death, and therefore does not qualify as
    renewed, low-level violence or war. In my article I addressed the
    1998 Ethiopia-Eritrea conflict, which did cause a great number of
    deaths, but also ended remarkably quickly (after two years, compared
    with three decades for the civil war): indeed, interstate wars are
    typically extremely short relative to civil wars, and this is one
    key advantage to the "internationalization" of such conflicts. The
    Georgian-Russian conflict over South Ossetia in August 2008 further
    illustrates this point: active combat operations ended after only
    six days. The de facto states of South Ossetia and Abkhazia have
    obsequiously pandered to Russian interests since they achieved de facto
    independence in 1992 and 1993, respectively, explicitly recognizing
    Russia as their only security guarantee against the existential
    threat posed by Georgia. By building up deterrence, these states aim
    to avoid war, but this objective could be pursued only as a result
    of partition. The deterrence capability provided by the region's only
    superpower cannot prevent a rash, hot-headed president from launching
    an ill-fated invasion, but at least the war with South Ossetia ended
    quickly, and Tbilisi is unlikely to ever attempt such actions in the
    future. Further, the death count was below 1,000 (combined civilian
    and combat), meaning that even its label as a "war" is open to dispute.

    CONCLUSION My article aimed to build on the academic debate over
    partition and to draw out policy implications from those results. I
    provided a novel methodological approach that clarified the debate and
    challenged conventional wisdom. I also identified several theoretical
    strands that support partition as a solution to ethnic civil war.

    With regard to policy, Horowitz, Weisiger, and I agree that the
    international community will not sponsor forced population transfers
    at this time, and this limits the ability to promote partition as a
    solution to ethnic civil wars. We differ, however, in how we see the
    remaining implications for partition as a policy tool. Because ethnic
    civil wars separate warring ethnic groups, and partitions that largely
    separate ethnic groups create peaceful solutions, policymakers need to
    seriously consider drawing fresh borders to separate warring groups as
    much as possible. Ethnic civil wars have an extremely high recidivism
    rate during the first five years, and such violence typically harms
    civilians the most. Given the promising track record of partition
    during the same five-year period, it is imperative that policymakers
    seriously consider this option. They could begin with several ongoing
    ethnic conflicts, including those involving Israel, Kosovo, Lebanon,
    Sri Lanka, and Sudan.

    --Carter Johnson College Park, Maryland

    FOOTNOTES 1 Carter Johnson, "Partitioning to Peace: Sovereignty,
    Demography, and Ethnic Civil Wars," International Security, Vol. 32,
    No. 4 (Spring 2008), pp. 140-170, at p. 165. Further references to
    this article appear parenthetically in the text.

    2 Chaim D. Kaufmann, "When All Else Fails: Ethnic Population Transfers
    and Partitions in the Twentieth Century," International Security,
    Vol. 23, No. 2 (Fall 1998), pp. 120-156.

    3 Jack L. Snyder and Robert Jervis, "Civil War and the Security
    Dilemma," in Barbara F. Walter and Snyder, eds., Civil Wars,
    Insecurity, and Intervention (New York: Columbia University Press,
    1999), pp. 15-37.

    4 He then goes on to describe how forced population transfers occurred
    in Bangladesh as well. Johnson, "Partitioning to Peace," p. 163.

    5 In this context, it is unsurprising that population transfers
    for partition have generally been extremely violent. Radha Kumar,
    "The Troubled History of Partition," Foreign Affairs, Vol. 76, No. 1
    (January/February 1997), pp. 22-34.

    6 Johnson, "Partitioning to Peace," p. 143; and Nicholas Sambanis,
    "Partition as a Solution to Ethnic War: An Empirical Critique of the
    Theoretical Literature," World Politics, Vol. 52, No. 4 (July 2000),
    pp. 437-483.

    7 Human Rights Watch, Cynthia G. Brown and Farhad Karim, eds., Playing
    the "Communal Card": Communal Violence and Human Rights (New York:
    Human Rights Watch, April 1995),

    8 Human Rights Watch, ed., Bloodshed in the Caucasus: Violations of
    Humanitarian Law and Human Rights in the Georgia-South Ossetia Conflict
    (New York: Human Rights Watch, March 1992); and Human Rights Watch,
    Georgia/Abkhazia: Violations of the Law of War and Russia's Role in
    the Conflict (New York: Human Rights Watch, March 1995).

    9 Edmond J. Keller, "The United States, Ethiopia, and Eritrean
    Independence," in Amare Tekle, ed., Eritrea and Ethiopia: From Conflict
    to Cooperation (Lawrenceville, N.J.: Red Sea Press, 1994), pp. 169-170.

    10 The casualty levels undermine Johnston's claim that postpartition
    wars will be less serious. That a two-year war had almost two-thirds
    the casualties of a decade-and-a-half civil war further undermines
    the claim that postpartition wars will be "better" than postconflict
    wars in nonpartition situations. On the casualty totals, see Meredith
    R. Sarkees, "The Correlates of War Data on War: An Update to 1997,"
    Conflict Management and Peace Science, Vol. 18, No. 1 (Spring 2000),
    pp. 123-144.

    11 Kaufmann, "When All Else Fails."

    12 James D. Fearon, "Separatist Wars, Partition, and World Order,"
    Security Studies, Vol. 13, No. 4 (Summer 2004), pp. 394-415. Fearon
    also notes that a general policy of partition would undermine the
    taboo against encouraging the breakup of opposing states, leading to
    more conflictual international relations.

    1 Carter Johnson, "Partitioning to Peace: Sovereignty, Demography,
    and Ethnic Civil Wars," International Security, Vol. 32, No. 4 (Spring
    2008), pp. 140-170. Additional references to this article appear in
    parentheses in the text.

    2 This line of thought was initially expressed by John Mearsheimer and
    Stephen Van Evera. Mearsheimer and Van Evera, "When Peace Means War:
    The Partition That Dare Not Speak Its Name," New Republic, December
    18, 1995, pp. 16-21. But it was developed first by Chaim Kaufmann,
    "Possible and Impossible Solutions to Ethnic Civil Wars," International
    Security, Vol. 20, No. 4 (Spring 1996), pp. 136-175.

    3 I defined "deadly conflict renewal" as renewal of combat leading
    to at least twenty-five deaths.

    4 Alexander B. Downes, "The Holy Land Divided: Partition as a Solution
    to Ethnic Wars," Security Studies, Vol. 10, No. 4 (Summer 2001),
    pp. 58-116.

    5 Barbara F. Walter, Committing to Peace: The Successful Settlement
    of Civil Wars (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 2002).

    6 Thomas Chapman and Phil G. Roeder, "Partition as a Solution to Wars
    of Nationalism: The Importance of Institutions," American Political
    Science Review, Vol. 101, No. 4 (November 2007), pp. 677-691.
Working...
X