Announcement

Collapse
No announcement yet.

Some Theoretical Considerations

Collapse
X
 
  • Filter
  • Time
  • Show
Clear All
new posts

  • Some Theoretical Considerations

    SOME THEORETICAL CONSIDERATIONS
    by Ronald Grigor Suny, [email protected]

    Revues.org
    http://ifpo.revues.org/index477.html
    May 29 2009

    Palestine is a denied country, and Palestinians a denied people. Their
    very existence, place on the globe, history, culture, and right to
    a homeland remain an open question. Very often in the United States
    one hears the rhetorical question - in which the answer is implied -
    "doesn't Israel have the right to exist? And, therefore, the right
    to defend itself?" But the question is almost never asked - at least
    I have never heard it in my own country - "doesn't Palestine have a
    right to exist and Palestinians the right to defend themselves?"

    2Where does that right to exist come from? From might? Might
    is right, say the realists going back to Thucydides. From simple
    demography? We are here, and we are a majority of the population, so
    say those democratic and socialist defenders of the right of national
    self-determination. From having gotten to a piece of the world's real
    estate first? So say the primordialist defenders of mythical histories
    that argue from ancient texts that we were here first and that gives
    us the right to this land no matter who in the intervening millennia
    came and went from this territory. Perhaps from the international
    community? Or from the struggle to make a nation, and by the making of
    that nation, to force upon the world the demand that they recognize
    the right of that nation to exist. That powerful claim is the card
    that stateless peoples have had to play, many successfully, in the
    last several centuries. Once the discourse of the nation became a
    principal threat to multinational empires based on conquest, dynasty,
    and the divine right to rule over inferior peoples, the claim could
    be made that nations had the right to rule themselves - and in order
    to do that they needed a place on the earth, a territory of their own,
    and a state to guard and guarantee their present and future existence.

    3Territory, state, and nation, then, are intimately linked in the
    discourse of the nation, and in the fiercely competitive international
    environment, a nation would find it hard to exist for very long or
    very effectively without territory and state. The dispersed Jews of
    Europe discovered that link between nation, territory, and state with
    the invention of Zionism, and built their state on land on which for
    centuries other peoples had lived. In their search for security they
    reaped permanent war and the steady erosion of their more democratic,
    socialist, and humanitarian ideals.

    4Nations are neither ancient nor permanent. They are the products
    of the modern age, though often built on older traditions and
    cultures. Nations are communities of people who identify more closely
    with one another than with others, who believe they share a culture,
    and because of that shared culture they have the right to rule
    themselves, live in security on a specific territory (identified as
    the homeland), and in the best of situations have a state of their
    own. This unique link of culture and politics is what makes the modern
    nation different from earlier political communities that had other
    forms of justification for government - God willed it or I conquered
    you or my father ruled and therefore I should as well (divine rule,
    conquest, dynasty).

    5Nations are particular forms ofidentification. Therefore, I should
    say a few words about identity. Identity is understood here as
    "a provisional stabilization of a sense of self or group that is
    formed in actual historical time and space, in evolving economies,
    polities, and cultures, as a continuous search for some solidity in
    a constantly shifting world - but without closure, without forever
    naturalizing or essentializing the provisional identities arrived at"
    (Suny 1999/2000, p. 144). Yet, at the same time, when people talk about
    identity their language excludes a sense of historical construction
    or provisionality and instead almost always accepts the present
    identity as fixed, singular, bounded, internally harmonious, distinct
    from others at its boundaries, and marked by historical longevity,
    if not rooted in nature. In other words, instead of seeing identity
    as something shifting and situational, people in ordinary language
    tend to primordialized and essentialized identities.

    6This loss of a processual sense of identification taking place over
    time is particularly acute in the rhetoric about national identity,
    which has become the universal category for modern political
    communities marked by a purportedly shared culture. Like other
    identifications, nations can be thought of as arenas in which people
    dispute who they are, argue about boundaries, who is in or out of the
    group, where the "homeland" begins and ends, what the "true" history
    of the nation is, what is "authentic" about being national and what
    is to be rejected. Nations are articulated through the stories people
    tell about themselves. The narrative is most often a tale of origins
    and continuity, often of sacrifice and martyrdom, but also of glory
    and heroism (Suny 1999/2000, p. 145; Suny 2001, p. 335-358).

    7Where do identifications come from? Identities are generated both
    internally by actors and externally by elites and states. Post-colonial
    studies in particular have contributed enormously to our understanding
    of how mapping, naming, census categories, statistical enumeration,
    and other practices of the modern state have delineated and fixed the
    more fluid distinctions generated by people, turning blurry differences
    into more visible, seemingly unalterable differences (Anderson 1991,
    p. 163-185, Cohen 1996, Scott 1998).

    8More elusive as sources of identification, but perhaps most
    influential, are the self-generated subjective identifications that
    individuals make spontaneously and that stem from the most local
    locations - family relations, birth position in the family, sexual
    preferences, etc. Here proximity, distance, and length of time of
    relationship are key influences on stable and lasting associations
    and networks, whether kinship, friendship, collegial, or national,
    and have powerful determining effects on identification with groups,
    location, and nation. Self-identification is seldom a simple rational
    calculation but is deeply implicated in emotional attachments and
    subjective preferences.

    1 Brubaker and Cooper dispute the analytical validity of the
    term "identity" and propose (...) 9Finally, identifications are
    influenced by the discursive context in which people find themselves,
    the pervasive narratives that surround them, giving shape to their
    perceptions and understandings of the world. Although identification
    "invites specification of the agents that do the identifying,"
    as Brubaker and Cooper put it, "identification does not require
    a specifiable 'identifier'; it can be pervasive and influential
    without being accomplished by discrete, specified persons or
    institutions. Identification can be carried more or less anonymously
    by discourses or public narratives"1 (Brubaker and Cooper 2000, p. 16).

    10Narrative - the stories we tell about ourselves and others - is
    central to identity formation, as Margaret R. Somers reminds us:

    [I]t is through narrativity that we come to know, understand, and
    make sense of the social world, and it is through narratives and
    narrativity that we constitute our social identities... [A]ll of us
    come to be who we are (however ephemeral, multiple, and changing)
    by being located or locating ourselves (usually unconsciously) in
    social narratives rarely of our own making (Somers 1994, p. 606).

    11Somers goes on to specify four dimensions of narrativity:
    ontological, public, conceptual, and metanarrativities. Ontological
    narratives are about who we are and why we do what we do. Public
    narratives are those attached to cultural and institutional formations
    beyond the single individual, to intersubjective networks of
    institutions. Conceptual narrativity is the concepts and explanations
    that are constructed by social researchers, such as "society,"
    "culture," "structure," and "agency." And, finally, metanarratives
    or master narratives are the grand overriding stories in which we
    are historically embedded, such as stories of the nation, progress,
    decadence, or the end of history (Somers 1994, p. 617-620). Identities,
    then, are always formed within broad discourses, universes of available
    meanings, and are related to the historic positionings of the subjects
    involved, which are themselves constituted and given meaning by the
    identity makers.

    12Some theorists are already asking: why bother about identity? Why
    indulge in so much theorizing about such an abstract and
    contested term? The payoff of employing the concept of identity is
    threefold. Sensitivity to the fluidity of identities, as well as the
    naturalizing tendencies of identity-talk, helps the researcher avoid,
    first, essentialism and, second, reification. Essentialism may be
    defined as the attribution of behavior or thinking to the intrinsic,
    fundamental nature of a person, collectivity, or state. Identity
    theory proposes an alternative to essentialist models of people
    or social groups by claiming that rather than having a single,
    given, relatively stable identity, persons and groups have multiple,
    fluid, situational identities that are produced in intersubjective
    understandings. Reification "is the apprehension of the products of
    human activity as if they were something else than human products -
    such as facts of nature, results of cosmic laws, or manifestations of
    divine will. Reification implies that man is capable of forgetting
    his own authorship of the human world, and further, that the
    dialectic between man, the producer, and his products is lost to
    consciousness. The reified world is...experienced by man as a strange
    facility, and opus alienum over which he has no control rather than as
    the opus proprium of his own productive activity" (Berger and Luckman
    1966, p. 89). Identity theory instead emphasizes the historical
    and contextual generation of both categories and their effects. In
    this approach human agency remains central to the production of
    identities. Third, identity as a focus of analysis displaces interest
    as the unmediated causal explanation for action. Instead of appealing
    to a notion of a universal social agent that acts because of inherent
    interests in predictable ways in similar circumstances, theories
    of identity propose that predictability from interest must consider
    the ways in which individuals or groups of people in similar social
    positions with similar experiences identify themselves, how stable or
    unstable that identity is, and how fractures or multiple commitments
    will affect ideas of interest. This is an important move toward
    contextualizing, historicizing, and relativizing actions. Interests
    themselves should be seen as tied to identities - what we think we
    need is linked to who we think we are - and are themselves affected by
    historic positions discursively constituted and embedded in narratives.

    13Although individual senses of the self may differ radically from
    one society or culture to another, it is possible to assert that
    there cannot be a group that does not possess some sense of shared
    commonality, even if just being in a certain room at ten past twelve,
    and a sense of difference with others, those in another room or with
    no room of their own. Cohesion of a group may depend on the particular
    articulation of the sense of commonality, and here a sense of shared
    past experience, that is, history, becomes important as a record of
    what binds the group together and distinguishes it from others.

    14Nations are particular forms of collectivity that are constituted by
    a process of creating histories. Just as there are few groups without a
    sense of continuity, so there can be no nations without a sense of its
    own history. History contributes in several significant ways. Like
    the genealogies of ancient and medieval kings, history provides
    ancestry that legitimizes present-day loyalties. The art of "seizing
    and recording one's own history," writes Natalie Zemon Davis, not only
    contributes "a deepened sense of identity" but "an affective-political
    gain in enablement" (Davis 1994, p. 21). National histories followed
    religious histories and borrowed modes and modalities from them. Both
    were written to advocate a particular sense of fidelity; light and
    dark images of the self and other distanced those within the fold
    and those outside; a sense of enemies, persecution, sacrifices,
    martyrdom, heretics, and true believers passed from the lives of the
    saints and the clerical chronicles to the stories of the nation. The
    longue durée of the past also gives this particular form of imagined
    community a potent claim to territory, the "homeland," which the people
    constituted as nation argues that it held first. The national history
    is one of continuity, antiquity of origins, heroism and past greatness,
    martyrdom and sacrifice, victimization and overcoming of trauma. It is
    a story of struggle, the empowerment of the people, the realization of
    the ideals of popular sovereignty. While in some cases national history
    is seen as development toward realization, in others it is imagined
    as decline and degeneration away from proper development. In either
    case an interpretation of history with a proper trajectory is implied.

    15Beyond the specific narratives of particular nations is the
    metanarrative or discourse of the nation, the cluster of ideas
    and understandings that came to surround the signifier "nation"
    in modern times (roughly post-1750). This available universe
    of meanings allowed for the power of nations and nationalism to
    constitute collective loyalties, legitimize governments, mobilize
    and inspire people to fight, kill, and die for their country. This
    cluster of ideas includes the conviction that humanity is naturally
    divided into separate and distinct nationalities or nations. Members
    of a nation reach full freedom and fulfillment of their essence by
    developing their national identity and culture, and their identity
    with the nation is superior to all other forms of identity - class,
    gender, individual, familial, tribal, regional, imperial, dynastic,
    religious, racial, or state patriotic. Though the nation may be divided
    or gradated along several axes, it is politically and civilly (under
    the law) made up of equals. All national members share common origins,
    historical experiences, interests, and culture, which may include
    language and religion, and have an equal share in the nation. The
    discourse of the nation both acknowledges that each nation is unique,
    with its own separate past, present, and destiny, yet recognizes the
    developmental process that gives every nation the conviction that
    the nation is always present, though often concealed, to be realized
    fully over time in a world of states in which the highest form is a
    world of nation-states. The national may be in people unconsciously
    and may need to be brought forth or willed into consciousness, but in
    this discourse the nation is never completely subjective but always
    has a base in the real world.

    16Like other discourses, talk about and everyday embodiments of the
    nation both constitute the felt presence of the national and hide the
    fractures, divisions, and relations of power within the nation. But,
    then, that is why intellectuals and politicians, military bands and
    postage stamps, have so much work to do. Ultimately more fragile
    than we usually admit, the nation must constantly be reproduced in
    thousands of ways until it becomes as ordinary and quotidian as the
    water in which fish swim. Ultimately, ordinary people must join in
    that daily plebiscite of which Ernest Renan spoke, or what at times
    seemed so evident and permanent can give way to more tangible concerns.

    17But if the theorists of nationalism are correct when they say that
    the nation is in a real sense an "imagined community," why then
    do people persist to think of it as a hard reality, an ancient,
    continuous, primordial community that moves through time with its
    fundamental essence intact. The disjuncture between the constructivist
    convictions of nationalism theorists and the nationalists' belief
    in firm, real, essential characteristics of nations is not easily
    resolved by a simple exposure of the processes by which national
    histories and group distinctions are constructed. Primordial identity
    construction cannot be reduced to a mistake, a self-deception, or false
    consciousness. Rather theorists need to appreciate the important work
    that primordialism and essentialism perform.

    18Identification with the nation need not entail a move to
    primordialism, though, I hope to show, there is a selective affinity
    between nation, essentialism, and primordialism. The nation is an
    affective community, a community of shared feeling, and of individual
    emotional attachment to the group, one that has an existence
    independent of oneself and one's individual mortality. National
    identity is an act of subscription to a continuous community with
    a past and a future, a shared destiny. Yael Tamir, the theorist
    of liberal nationalism, claims that national membership, "unlike
    membership in a gender, class, or region, thus enables an individual to
    find a place not only in the world in which he or she lives, but also
    in an uninterrupted chain of being. Nationhood promotes fraternity
    both among fellow members and across generations. It endows human
    action with meaning that endures over time, thus carrying a promise
    of immortality" (Tamir 1995, p.

    437). When they work, nations must feel like a community with powerful
    subjective identifications of individuals with the whole. While
    nations to some extent depend on free individual choice, as Margaret
    Canovan notes, "that choice is nevertheless experienced as a destiny
    transcending individuality; it turns political institutions into a
    kind of extended family inheritance, although the kinship ties in
    question are highly metaphorical" (Canovan 1996, p. 69). Nation works
    most powerfully precisely when people are unaware that they have made
    contingent choices and feel that they are acting in accord with a
    natural order. Calculation is suppressed and feelings are heightened.

    19Like the idea of family, so the nation form provides clear
    boundaries of a community within which social goods can be properly
    distributed. In social science the very process of constituting
    a political community in the form of a nation has been seen as a
    necessity for democratic politics. Democracies in particular require
    a clearly defined, bounded population that then has the right to
    be represented (Rustow 1970, p. 337-363). Nation is a convenient
    and powerful form of identification that speaks precisely to these
    conditions. "Democratic discourse," writes Canovan, "requires not only
    trust and common sympathies but the capacity to act as a collective
    people, to undertake commitments and to acquire obligations" (Canovan
    1996, p. 44). While nationalism (because of its affiliations with
    revolution and the Left) was suspect in the minds of many Western
    policymakers during the first great decolonization after World War II,
    political analysts were even more troubled by tribalism and social
    fragmentation than they were with efforts of nationalists to construct
    new, coherent communities on the model of Western nations. Political
    integration of localities or tribes into coherent nations was part of
    the project of modernization, the prerequisite to democratization,
    lauded by its theorists (Geertz 1963; Apter 1963; Coleman 1958;
    Bendix 1977).

    20As sensible as the fluidity of constructivism is for theorists,
    in the actual world of group identifications and distinctions, a
    belief in sharp and relatively fixed distinctions between groups and
    predictable harmonies and homogeneities within groups gives a person
    an easy and reliable map of a complex and changing world. This kind of
    mental map provides a degree of predictability in an insecure world;
    it allows expectations of comfort with some and danger from others;
    and it permits different forms of treatment of those one considers
    like oneself from those who are considered different. In worse cases it
    licenses treatment of "others" in ways that one would not treat one's
    own. As the Armenian case demonstrates, essentialist articulations
    of identity are more intense paradoxically when identities seem to
    be threatened. Even though immutable identities should be the least
    threatened, as if unconvinced by their own rhetoric primordialist
    nationalists fear the loss of identity and seek actively to intervene
    to save it. And they attempt to save it precisely by shoring up the
    internal harmonies within the nation and policing the boundaries of
    national identity, sharpening the distinctions between those within
    and those without.

    21But the need for meaning, mental maps, or effective boundaries
    and collective commitments for polities only partially explains the
    power of the nation form and the turn toward primordialism. National
    identity, like others, is seldom purely about what is convenient or
    rational. Group or personal identities may be strategic starting
    points from which people act but they are also emotionally
    generated. Identities are most often a complex combination of
    reason and affect, learning and experience from a variety of
    sources. Subjectively experienced, they are a starting point for
    people's strategic choices. People may act rationally to realize
    their preferences, but those preferences are intimately tied to the
    identities that people have constructed or that have been constituted
    for them.

    2 The study of emotions and nationalism is just getting underway. See
    for example Petersen 2002.

    22National identities are saturated with emotions that have been
    created through teaching, repetition, and daily reproduction until
    they become common sense. The very rhetoric of nationalism reveals
    its affective base. Armenians speak constantly of betrayal, either by
    traitors within (like my ancient namesake Vasak Siuni who "betrayed"
    the martyr Vartan Mamikonian in 451 C.E.!), or by foreign powers,
    or by their own, treacherous imperial overlords. Their history
    is replete with invasions and massacres, of near disappearances,
    culminating in the Genocide of the early twentieth century. Yet they
    have survived! These tropes - betrayal, treachery, threats from others,
    and survival - are embedded in familiar emotions - anxiety, fear,
    insecurity, and pride. For many post-colonial nations, governments
    must construct or reconstruct a national narrative that deals with
    the anxieties of cultural loss, the need for national pride, and
    the insecurity of a formerly colonized people now free from but in
    many cases still dependent on their recent colonizers. For Tamir, the
    need for the nation involves a perception of shared fate that becomes
    an answer to the neurosis, alienation, and meaninglessness of modern
    times. Here again is emotion. The dreads of personal oblivion, the need
    for redemption, salvation, eternity are all answered in the nation.2

    23The nation need not have been primordialized historically, and
    yet over time it was, until primordial ethnonations became the
    dominant template for nations. If not in the first generation of
    nation-formation (the new revolutionary nations of France and the
    Americas), then certainly in the second and subsequent generations,
    the nation came to represent a primordial community that passes
    continuously through time. The category "nation," like those of
    class and race, acquired its own style of imagination, increasingly
    over time about deep, essential differences between nations and
    fixed, continuous cores within them - whether such distinctions or
    harmonies existed or not. Certain "objective" criteria of nation -
    language most importantly - provided the clear markers of boundaries,
    inclusion and exclusion. As Etienne Balibar puts it, "the illusion is
    twofold. It consists in believing that the generations which succeed
    one another over centuries on a reasonably stable territory, under a
    reasonably univocal designation, have handed down to each other an
    invariant substance. And it consists in believing that the process
    of development from which we select aspects retrospectively, so as
    to see ourselves as the culmination of that process, was the only
    one possible, that is, it represented a destiny" (Balibar 1991, p. 86).

    24National identity construction has most powerfully been about a
    single, unitary identity, not a multiplicity of self-understandings,
    embedded in a long history and attached to a specific territory. The
    power of that identity lay within the discourse of the nation, which
    justified both territorial possession and statehood to those with prior
    and exclusive claims, based on language, culture, or race. In a world
    of competitors for territory and political power, primordialism was a
    practical, even necessary, solution to the difficulty of establishing
    such prior or exclusive claims. Since prenational ethnic and religious
    communities do not map neatly with modern nations, and nations
    themselves are inherently unstable categories, primordialism and
    essentialism do the hard work of reifying the nation. Identities might
    be fluid but in the real world of politics the players act as if they
    are immutable, both for strategic reasons and emotional satisfaction.

    25What is not recognized in the rush to nationhood is just how much
    work by intellectuals, activists, and state administrators goes into
    the forging of new nations. Nationalists often strive to get history
    "right." In their "objectivist" reading of the past - showing the
    past as "it actually was" they set themselves up as representing the
    only true account. This pretension to an untroubled authenticity of
    a single reading is a powerful claim to the legitimacy of the nation
    and particular claims to territory and statehood. But it does not come
    without costs. If the nation is real, ancient, and continuous, then in
    its own view (and in the discourse of the nation more generally), its
    claims to sovereignty is unique, uncontested, and not to be shared. The
    road is open to exclusivist, homogeneous nations that in our ethnically
    mixed, fluid, changing world require desperate policies of deportation
    and ethnic cleansing to secure. Constructivists propose a more open
    view of national history in which human actions and interventions
    have made the world the way it is today. If the lines between peoples
    are blurred and shifting, if many possible claimants to a particular
    piece of the world's real estate are allowed, then we can conceive
    of political communities in the future that permit cohabitation with
    shared sovereignties in a "national" space.

    26No nation in the modern world can survive without a space of its
    own, a territory on which to build its state and foster its cultural
    connectiveness. But the way the nation is imagined has profound
    consequences for the imagination of the territorial homeland as
    well. If the homeland is imagined as the exclusive property of one
    ethnic or religious group, then it necessarily leads to subordination
    of other groups or their assimilation or their physical elimination
    from the national territory. It is no accident that ethnic cleansing
    and/or genocide have been the foundational moments of many modern
    nation states, among them Australia, the United States, Turkey,
    Israel, and the list goes on and on. In some parts of the world,
    like the former Soviet Union, an internationalist empire left in its
    ashes fifteen independent states, each of them clinging to their own
    national territories, each defining the state in terms of their own
    ethnic nation. Not much sharing is going on in Armenia, Azerbaijan,
    Georgia, or many other republics.

    27But if the nation is imagined as inclusive, as tolerant of difference
    - religious and ethnic - then the territory too is open to a diverse
    population. The form and style of national imagination, the content of
    the national narrative, is central to whether one can share territory
    with others. Posing the question that way may seem utopian at the
    present time, particularly in the Middle East, where borders drawn
    by imperial powers have divided people into states seeking nations,
    where the colonizers appear determined to assert their influence long
    after their empires have fallen, and where the nation-state form has
    not proven very effective in delivering security and prosperity to
    most of the peoples of the region. At the moment we seem to be stuck
    with one people, one nation, one state. Some day, perhaps coming
    from the cradle of ancient civilizations, there will be new ways
    to imagine states - states larger and more inclusive than current
    nation-states. The task of intellectuals and political actors, then,
    in this time of troubles must be to think creatively how history,
    identity, and territory might be re-imagined so that nation-form works
    less to divide us one from another and more toward living together.

    BibliographieAnderson B., 1991: Imagined Communities: Reflections on
    the Origins and Spread of Nationalism, London, Verso Press.

    Apter D., and Eckstein H., 1963: Comparative Politics: A Reader,
    London, Free Press of Glencoe.

    Balibar E., 1991: Â" The Nation Form: History and Ideology Â",
    in Balibar, e. and Wallerstein, I., (eds.), Race, Nation, Class:
    Ambiguous Identities, London, Verso,

    Bendix R., 1977: Max Weber: An Intellectual Portrait, Berkeley,
    University of California Press.

    Berger P., and Luckmann T., 1966: The Social Construction of Reality,
    New York, Doubleday.

    Brubaker R., and Cooper F., 2000: Â" Beyond Identity Â", Theory and
    SocietyXXIX, p.147.

    Canovan M., 1996: Nationhood and Political Theory, Cheltenham, UK
    and Brookfield, US, Edward Elgar.

    Cohen B., 1996: Colonialism and its Forms of Knowledge: The British
    in India, Princeton, Princeton University Press.

    Coleman J., 1958: Nigerian Background to Nationalism, Berkeley,
    University of California Press.

    Davis N., 1994: Â" Who Owns History? Â", Studia HistoricaLXI, p.19-34.

    Geertz C., 1963:Old Societies and New States: The Quest for Modernity
    in Asia and Africa, New York, The Free Press.

    Petersen R., 2002: Understanding Ethnic Violence: Fear, Hatred,
    and Resentment in Twentieth-Century Eastern Europe, Cambridge, UK,
    Cambridge University Press.

    Rustow D., 1970: Â" Transitions to Democracy: Towards a Dynamic Model
    Â", Comparative PoliticsII (3), p. 337-363.

    Scott J., 1998: Seeing like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve
    the Human Condition have Failed, New Haven and London, Yale University
    Press.

    Somers M., 1994: Â" The Narrative Constitution of Identity: A
    Relationship and Network Approach Â", Theory and SocietyXXIII (5),
    p. 605-649.

    Suny R., 1999/2000: Â" Provisional Stabilities: The Politics of
    Identities in Post-Soviet EurasiaÂ", International Securityxxiv (3),
    p. 139-178.

    Suny R., 2001: Â" History Â", in MotylA. (ed.), Encyclopedia of
    Nationalism, San Diego, CA, and London, Academic Press, p. 335-358.

    Tamir Y., 1995: Â" The Enigma of Nationalism Â", World PoliticsXLVII,
    p. 418-440.

    Notes1 Brubaker and Cooper dispute the analytical validity of the term
    "identity" and propose substitute terms, such as identification,
    self-understanding, and commonality. They make a persuasive case
    for use of the term "identification" as an active processual term,
    but my own use of identity preserves the actual ambiguity of the term
    "identity" and is directed at investigating the tension between the
    analytical and practical uses of the term that they articulate so well.

    2 The study of emotions and nationalism is just getting underway. See
    for example Petersen 2002.

    Pour citer cet articleRéférence papier Ronald Grigor Suny, Â"
    Some Theoretical Considerations Â", in Roger Heacock (dir.), Temps
    et espaces en Palestine, Beyrouth, Liban, Institut francais du
    Proche-Orient (Â" Ã~Itudes contemporaines Â", no25), 2008, p. 31-41.

    Référence électronique Ronald Grigor Suny, Â" Some Theoretical
    Considerations Â", in Roger Heacock (dir.), Temps et espaces en
    Palestine, Beyrouth, Liban, Institut francais du Proche-Orient
    (Â" Ã~Itudes contemporaines Â", no25), 2008, [En ligne],
    mis en ligne le 28 mai 2009, Consulté le 29 mai 2009. URL :
    http://ifpo.revues.org/index477.html

    AuteurRona ld Grigor Suny Professor of history, University of
    Michigan. Emeritus professor of history and political Science,
    University of Chicago.
    From: Baghdasarian
Working...
X