Announcement

Collapse
No announcement yet.

Theriault: The Final Stage Of Genocide: Consolidation

Collapse
X
 
  • Filter
  • Time
  • Show
Clear All
new posts

  • Theriault: The Final Stage Of Genocide: Consolidation

    THERIAULT: THE FINAL STAGE OF GENOCIDE: CONSOLIDATION
    By Henry Theriault

    http://www.hairenik.com/weekly/2009/10/ 11/theriault-the-final-stage-of-genocide-consolida tion/
    October 11, 2009

    This essay is an analysis of the Turkish-Armenian protocol process in
    relation to the Armenian Genocide. I say "protocol process" because
    mere analysis of the protocols themselves cannot be meaningful. The
    protocols exist within a complex historical, cultural, political, and
    geopolitical context dominated by genocide and its aftermath. It is
    impossible to interpret accurately the meaning of particular elements
    of the protocols without reference to that context.

    Before I offer my analysis, I must point out that there has emerged
    a certain conceptual muddle in recent self-declared "objective" or
    "rational" evaluations of the protocols. I am especially concerned
    by Asbed Kotchikian's neutralist analysis and David Davidian's
    claimed "rational" analysis, both of which dismiss much of the recent
    diasporan discourse on the protocols that challenges their value and
    legitimacy (Kotchikian, "The Armenian-Turkish Protocols and Public
    (Dis)Content," Armenian Weekly On-line, October 4, 2009, and Davidian,
    "Turkish-Armenian Protocols: Reality and Irrationality," Armenian
    Weekly On-line, October 1, 2009).

    The conceptual muddle is this: Neutrality is not inherently
    objectivity and dispassion is not inherently rationality. In fact,
    neutrality itself is a position that can be biased or irrational,
    if the facts and logic call for taking a position one way or
    another on an issue. Furthermore, a person who chooses to advocate a
    position in strong terms is not by that fact automatically biased or
    irrational. Rationality-logic-is a form of thought in which reasons
    are given in support of a claim. Far from it being illogical to take a
    position on an issue, reasonable people have a moral responsibility to
    take positions if the facts and reason warrant doing so. The question
    of rationality is simply the question of whether one provides reasoning
    (facts and logical connection of the facts to the position advocated)
    to support one's position. Unequivocal advocacy of a position, no
    matter how "all or nothing" (to quote Davidian), is not inherently
    irrational. A viewpoint is non-rational if it is not supported by
    logically connected reasons in support of the position or supported by
    facts that are not convincingly connected to the position advocated. A
    position is irrational if it contradicts or culpably ignores known
    evidence and the logical connections of that evidence to the question
    at hand. While of course there are irrational and biased individuals
    in any large group, overall, the numerous dissenting Armenian voices
    rejecting the protocols present rational arguments based on factual
    evidence for rejection. While one might challenge the logic and dispute
    the claimed facts, the fact that some rational people disagree with
    rejection of the protocols does not mean that those who reject them
    are irrational.

    Perhaps with some dramatic irony, in his own thinking Davidian himself
    presents us with a very good example of irrationality. In the opening
    sections of his piece, he states that if Armenia chooses to reject
    international pressure to "discuss historical issues" (read: discuss
    whether a genocide happened) with Turkey, then the situation will be
    analogous to Slobodan Milosevic's refusal to stop "ethnic cleansing"
    (does Davidian mean in 1995 in Bosnia or in 1999 in Kosovo?) because
    he believed (most genocide perpetrators, as contemporaneous genocide
    deniers, do) that the Serbs "didn't start it." Davidian points out that
    Serbs were bombed and were foolish not to yield to the pressure as
    Armenia appears poised to. Thus, Armenians today would be irrational
    not to cave to the international pressure being applied to them. But,
    an analogy is the presentation of a situation, argument, or event
    (1) that is emotionally, politically, culturally, etc., neutral for
    the author/speaker and/or his/her audience and (2) that has strong
    relevant structural similarities to a situation, argument, or event to
    which the author/speaker and/or audience have emotional, political,
    cultural, etc., connections to. The goal is to allow dispassionate
    analysis of the latter situation, in order to see things that
    proximity and emotion obscure. An analogy depends on the structural
    similarity between the things analogized. But Davidian is comparing
    (1) a post-genocidal victim state and society that have attempted
    to engage the international community, including Turkey, on the past
    genocide (though of course not in the way the perpetrator, committed to
    denial, would like) with (2) a perpetrator state actively engaged in
    an act of genocide and organized around pathological rationalization
    of that genocide despite legitimate international objection to and
    pressure against it. That Davidian finds it logically valid to liken
    the situation of the Armenian state and society today to Serbia at
    the time it was committing genocide does not call into !

    question tocols but to Davidian's own pretentions to logical
    analysis. When the issue is negotiation over the truth about a
    genocide, by definition the logical positioning of a state that is
    heir to a victim society cannot be analogous to the positioning of a
    perpetrator state. To suggest that Armenia would face military force
    for not signing the protocols in the way that Serbia faced bombing
    because it was participating in genocide makes no sense. Indeed, the
    real lesson regarding Serbia is that a state can do much more against
    international pressure than Armenia is doing-indeed, participate in
    a genocide for three years-without being subjected to any meaningful
    outside intervention for quite awhile, which is the opposite message
    from what Davidian suggests.

    Let me qualify this somewhat. A victim state cannot be analogized
    to a perpetrator state in so far as the former is a victim state. If
    Armenia were to commit a genocide itself, then this would be the basis
    of an analogy between it and Serbia. In addition, if a particular
    individual or group within Armenia adopted a denialist position and
    agenda similar to that in Turkey, there could be some kind of analogy
    based on this as well. But this is not what Davidian is claiming.

    Now to the analysis. It has become a truism that "denial is the
    final stage of genocide." Greg Stanton, the former president of the
    International Association of Genocide Scholars, for instance, asserts
    this in his stage theory of genocide. But, as with many truisms,
    this one is false. That denial is present long after a genocide
    does not mean that denial is the final stage of a genocide. Denial
    is present at many stages of a genocide. With very few exceptions,
    denials are issued by perpetrators while they are committing genocide.

    Denials are typically offered immediately after a genocide to prevent
    accountability of individual perpetrators as well as the perpetrator
    society. One need only look at the court transcripts of trials of
    Rwanda or Bosnia Genocide perpetrators to confirm this. And, denials
    are offered in the long-term aftermath of a genocide to cover up the
    historical facts. The motives for this include such things as the
    desperate desire to preserve the legitimacy of an ideology and linked
    sense of group identity in the face of exposure of the genocidal nature
    of that ideology, the desire to prevent reparations in terms of land
    and/or wealth, and a sense of shame among members of the perpetrator
    society that is not coupled with a moral commitment to rectify the
    impact of the past. Given this, denial is dominant in the long-term
    aftermath of genocide, but it is an instrument for deeper goals.

    The last stage of genocide is consolidation of the gains of the
    genocide. In this stage, the perpetrator group tries to establish the
    results of the genocide as the status quo, rather than a persisting
    violation requiring rectification. It uses denial as a tool, because
    if deniers convince enough people that a genocide did not happen or
    is doubtful, then these people will see the existing post-genocidal
    state of affairs as legitimate. They will see the small population of
    the victims, their political weakness, their cultural tenuousness,
    their relative poverty, and so forth as the natural result of an
    uneventful history. If a perpetrator society can effectively deny the
    past genocide, it will succeed in keeping what the direct perpetrators
    gained for it.

    To the credit of Stanton and others who view denial as the last stage
    of genocide, it is typically the dominant activity of the perpetrators
    in the long-term aftermath of genocide. What is more, even when the
    possibility of material rectification is lessened, the perpetrators
    or their progeny typically aggressive seek to cover up even the
    knowledge of the genocide, to achieve full erasure of its victims and
    full validation of the perpetrators such that they do not even pay
    a moral price for the past. Such figures as Elie Wiesel and Israel
    Charny have commented on this attempted final conceptual erasure.

    But, sometimes denial fails to change perceptions of history or
    at least to produce a stalemate in which the issue is viewed as a
    perpetual and irresolvable conflict between two parties over history,
    which is a victory for perpetrators in so far as they are allowed to
    keep the material, political, ideological, and cultural gains of the
    genocide for the foreseeable future. In such a case, denial has become
    ineffective, but consolidation is still the goal. The perpetrator
    state will seek to consolidate the gains of the genocide in question
    by some other means.

    This is precisely what we are seeing with the new protocols. Denial
    has failed the Turkish state, and until April 2009 the pressure
    was mounting to deal with the legacy of the Armenian Genocide
    in a meaningful manner. That pressure had intensified especially
    over the past two years through the challenges posed by activists,
    journalists, and intellectuals inside Turkey after the Hrant Dink
    assassination shocked morally-grounded members of Turkish society with
    the genocidal anti-Armenianism that had previously been rationalized
    by their government or hidden from their view. The stage was set for
    the kind of real transformation in Turkey that can be the only path
    toward a genuine improvement in Armenian-Turkish relations.

    The protocols are the last-ditch response by the Turkish government to
    protect and solidify the gains of the genocide. Through them, Turkey
    has gone from the brink of required justice to a potential victory
    deniers could only dream of three decades ago. What the protocols do
    is achieve agreement from the putative representative of the victim
    community that the perpetrator's successor state and society will
    never have to give up the land gained through the genocide nor make
    any material restitution for the horrific suffering imposed on the
    victim community, which still reverberates today. What the protocols
    ensure is that the weak and poor Armenia produced by the genocide will
    become the permanent state of Armenians, while the increased power,
    prestige, land, wealth, and ideological security the Turkish state
    and society gained through genocide will remain its. In other words,
    the protocols finish the Armenian Genocide as successfully as the
    pro-genocidal segment of today's Turkey ever could have hoped. The
    protocols are the last stage of the Armenian Genocide, the successful
    completion of the Armenian Genocide.

    It is telling that an important element of the protocols is the
    reinsertion of denial of the Armenian Genocide as a credible position
    by agreement of the Armenian government itself. This is the meaning of
    the provision for a historical commission to study the mutual history
    of the two protocol partners. Denial is the official position of
    the Turkish government and clearly the starting position for their
    participation in such a commission. The fact that the protocols
    do not specify that the commission will consider the issue of
    "the Armenian Genocide" shows that Turkey wants to maintain this
    position. Given that its government and academic leaders know full
    well a genocide occurred, there is no reason Turkey would not just
    admit the genocide if it were not intent on maintaining denial. As
    Roger Smith, the former president of the International Association of
    Genocide Scholars and current chair of the Academic Board of Directors
    of the Zoryan Institute, states in his Sept. 30 letter to Armenian
    President Sarkisian, Turkey would even be bound by its own laws to
    reject a finding of genocide by this historical commission. Of course,
    it is unlikely that the commission's membership will be constituted
    in such a way as to allow that result to emerge-we are sure to see
    Turkey insist on deniers as members of the commission. In this way,
    the denial campaign that has faltered and been widely discredited
    will be relegitimized within the process that has resulted from the
    denial's failure in the first place. The irony is thick here.

    For Armenians to acquiesce in this is not merely to betray the memories
    of those who died and those who survived. It is not merely to accept
    one of the great grand larcenies of history and the debilitating
    poverty that has resulted. It is to accept the permanence of the
    destruction of Armenian political, social, cultural, and economic
    life, rather than receive the rehabilitative rectification that world
    ethical and legal principles unequivocally recognize as the victims'
    desperate need and right.

    Davidian and others argue that Armenia and Armenians have no choice
    and should try to get what they can in the face of this inevitable
    destruction. But, if, as many in Armenia and outside have argued,
    Armenia's survival depends on some rectification of the genocide that
    continues to impact it materially,

    geopolitically, etc., then acquiescing is dangerous self-delusion. It
    is yet another instance of Armenians in a desperate situation giving
    up and embracing a thoughtless, irrational faith that those who have
    done them great harm in the past and present will somehow suddenly
    change utterly and things will work out. It is the mentality of
    the beaten, the destroyed, the resigned. It is the mentality that
    Armenian Genocide survivors rejected despite the horrific suffering
    they experienced. Can we do less now?

    Davidian claims that the geopolitical realities of Armenia's
    existence preclude it "from engaging in zero sum inanity, such as
    demanding an all-or-nothing state of affairs." The idea is that
    realism should replace ethical principle as the basis of Armenian
    decision-making. But, given the history with Turkey, given its clear
    intentions and absolute lack of repentance for the Armenian Genocide to
    the point where it cannot even recognize the genocide in the interest
    of negotiating better relations with Armenia, it would be truly
    "inane" to enter into an agreement that depends on Turkey working
    with Armenia in good faith. It is not just that it is wrong to trade
    recognition of the Armenian Genocide for some short-term economic
    benefit (which might prove illusory anyway); the trade cannot work by
    its very nature. The fact that the perpetrator successor state remains
    committed to denial of the genocide and thus to the acceptability of
    genocide as a tool against Armenians makes it impossible for it to
    enter a productive relationship with Armenia and Armenians. So long
    as the Turkish state and society remain unrepentant for the genocide,
    Armenians have no choice but to require an all-or-nothing state of
    affairs regarding the Armenian Genocide. It is Turkish denial and
    approval of genocide that forces Armenians into this position.

    Contrary to Davidian's assertion, such an all-or-nothing ethics-based
    approach that rejects coercion by the pressure of "interests"
    and power is anything but irrational. We need look no further than
    Plato's Republic and Gorgias to see advocacy of ethical principle
    over realpolitik by a thinker universally recognized as one of the
    most rational in human history. Of course, those who understand how
    social movements really work, how they succeed, will recognize this
    all-or-nothing strategy as quite practical, and not only because the
    squeaky wheel gets the oil or because pressing such demands pushes
    the compromise point of the negotiation further toward the goals of
    that squeaky wheel. It wasn't those who accepted segregation because
    it was backed by tremendous political, cultural, social, and military
    power whose view of race relations changed the United States; it was
    Malcolm X's and Martin Luther King's all-or-nothing challenges. India
    was not freed from the British because Gandhi compromised with the
    British, but because he asserted an all-or-nothing requirement for
    independence and dignity. What is striking about these examples-and
    many others from history-is that these all-or-nothing demands came
    from positions of great material, political, and military weakness and
    yet still succeeded because of the moral strength of the position of
    the "weak" vis-a-vis the "strong." Moral legitimacy is a great force
    in geopolitics and is the reliable ally of the weak, oppressed, and
    marginalized. It is the force that those committed to power politics,
    realpolitik, fear so desperately that they incessantly mock it as
    if whistling in the dark, ridiculing those who believe in it in the
    hope that they will stop believing and thus be tricked into giving up
    the most powerful tool of change. It is Armenia's one advantage today,
    and the present leadership, through unhistorical, naive "realpolitical"
    calculations of the web of power and interests around them, are about
    to squander it.

    Henry Theriault is a Professor of Philosophy at Worcester State
    College.
Working...
X